6
$\begingroup$

The Heine-Borel theorem for $\mathbb{R}^n$ states that a subset $K\subset\mathbb{R}^n$ is closed and bounded if and only if it is compact. (A set is said to be compact if every open cover of the set has a finite sub-cover). The standard method to show that closed- and boundedness implies compactness starts by enclosing $K$ in a box, and continually bisecting it until some or other contradiction is obtained. I have an alternative approach, but I am not entirely sure it works, and I would like to know if it seems possible to extend this to an arbitrary metric space (by replacing closed and bounded by sequentially compact) beyond that, I think its interesting that an inductive proof for it exists, so here it is:

Firstly, it is sufficient to prove that every closed ball centered at $0$ is compact, since one can always enclose a bounded set $K$ inside such a closed ball of radius $r$, $U(r)$, and append to any cover of $K$ the set $\mathbb{R}^n \setminus K$, and finding a finite subcover of the new cover is then equivalent to finding a finite subcover of the original cover.

The base case is trivial since $\mathbb{R}^{0}=\{0\}$ has only compact subsets. If we then assume that this theorem holds in $\mathbb{R}^k$, we will show that it holds in $\mathbb{R}^{k+1}$.

Now let $U(r)\subseteq \mathbb{R}^{k+1}$ be the closed ball of radius $r$ centered at the origin, and let $G$ be a cover for $U(r)$. Then we say that $l\in \mathbb{R}^+$ is reached if there is some finite subset $G'$ of $G$ such that

$$U(l) \subseteq \bigcup G' $$

Now define $w$ as supremum of those $l\leq r$ which are reached. Now we assume that $w<r$ and obtain a contradiction. Note that since

$$\partial U(w) \subseteq U(r) \subseteq \bigcup G $$

We have that $\partial U(w)$ is covered by $G$. But $\partial U(w)$ is a $k$-dimensional sphere, so it's upper (inclusive) hemisphere is homeomorphic to the closed ball in $\mathbb{R}^k$, which is compact by assumption, so there is a finite subset of $G$ which covers the upper hemisphere of $\partial U(w) $, the same is of course true for the lower hemisphere, so there is a finite subset of $G$, call it $G_0$, which covers $\partial U(w) $. It is then easy to show that $G_0\cup G'$, where $G'$ is a finite subset of $G$, covers an open ball with a radius larger than $w$ (the proof for this is included at the end) and thus it covers a closed ball with a radius larger than $w$, which is a contradiction, since $w$ was assumed to be the supremum of reached radii.

Some of my questions are, is this a known proof? Is it correct?

Proof that an open ball of radius larger than $w$ is covered by a finite subset of $G$:

To see why, it is sufficient to show that there is some $\delta>0$ such that for any $x\in\partial U(w)$, the open ball of radius $\delta$ is contained in some member of $G_0$. Suppose this is not true, then for any $\delta>0$ there is some $x\in\partial U(w)$ such that the open ball of radius $\delta$ is not contained in any member of $G_0$, we can in particular take the convergent sequence of $\delta_n=\frac{1}{n}$, which induces a sequence $(x_n)$ with elements in $\partial U(w)$, but because of sequential compactness, this sequence converges to some point$x_0\in\partial U(w)$ but this is a contradiction since $x_0$ is contained in some open ball of radius $\delta_0$ (because $G_0$ is an open cover for $\partial U(w)$) and so eventually the $x_n$'s will be within $\frac{\delta_0}{2}$ of $x_0$, but then each $x_n$ beyond this point is contained in an open ball of radius $\frac{\delta_0}{2}$, a contradiction, so there is some $\delta>0$ such that every point in $\partial U(w)$ is contained in the open ball of radius $\delta$ around that point. A routine application of the triangle inequality then shows that for any $|\varepsilon|\leq \frac{\delta}{2}$ we have

$$\partial U(w+\varepsilon) \in \bigcup G_0$$

Since there is some finite subset $G'\subseteq G$ such that

$$U\left(w-\frac{\delta}{2}\right)\subseteq \bigcup G' $$

So $G'\cup G_0$ covers $U(w+\frac{\delta}{2})$ which is the contradiction we required in the original proof

$\endgroup$
18
  • $\begingroup$ Is that the standard proof? The one I'm most familiar is showing that (1) If $K$ is closed and bounded, then since $[-N, N]^k$ is the product of compact spaces and thus compact itself, $K$ is also compact; (2) If $K$ is not closed, then $K$ is not compact (as, e.g., $\mathbb{R}^n$ is Hausdorff); and (3) If $K$ is not bounded, then the open cover $U_n = K\cap (-n, n)^k$ has no finite subcover. $\endgroup$
    – anomaly
    Commented Nov 10, 2023 at 17:25
  • $\begingroup$ @anomaly I think they're claiming it's a nonstandard proof. I've never seen it before but I like it a lot. I think there is one small detail left to fill in which is that $G$ finitely covers $U(w)$ - this is not immediate from coverage of $\partial U(w)$. $\endgroup$
    – FShrike
    Commented Nov 10, 2023 at 17:27
  • $\begingroup$ As for general theorems - yes, in any metric space there is a chain of equivalences: compact <-> sequentially compact <-> complete and totally bounded $\endgroup$
    – FShrike
    Commented Nov 10, 2023 at 17:28
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @anomaly, when I said generalise I was referring to the theorem that sequential compactness is equivalent to compactness for an arbitrary metric space, since I am aware that there are some broader notions of "dimension" in metric spaces, and if these satisfy the same condition as the normal dimension, i.e. that the boundary of an n-dimensional ball has a dimension of n-1, then one might be able to apply a similar argument, for other finite dimensional spaces $\endgroup$
    – Carlyle
    Commented Nov 10, 2023 at 20:07
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ One more point: "Now we assume that $w<r$ and obtain a contradiction." It is better to assume $w \le r$ and obtain a contradicton. This implies $w > r$, thus $r$ is reached and $U(r)$ is covered by finitely many elements of $G$. If we only know $w \ge r$, it requires once more to consider a finite subcover of $\partial U(r)$. $\endgroup$
    – Paul Frost
    Commented Nov 13, 2023 at 9:47

1 Answer 1

2
$\begingroup$

You correctly state

The standard method to show that closed- and boundedness implies compactness starts by enclosing $K$ in a box, and continually bisecting it until some or other contradiction is obtained.

Your alternative proof is absolutely correct. Its essential part is Proof that an open ball of radius larger than $w$ is covered by a finite subset of $G$. This is based on the fact that in metric space compactness is equivalent to sequential compactness. Although this is true, it seems to be a bit unsatisfactory because you invoke an argument of a new provenance ( not an open-cover-argument). We shall see later that this is essentially a variant of the tube lemma.

The tube lemma is easily proved by considering open covers. It is used to prove (inductively) that finite products of compact spaces are compact.

A variant of your proof is to show that that cubes $[-r,r]^n$ are compact. Step 1 is to prove that $[-r,r]$ is compact, step 2 is to use induction.

There are various proofs of the compactness of closed intervals $[a,b]$, and one of these proofs uses your "reached" argument which is very easy in this case. See How to prove every closed interval in R is compact?

Let us modify your proof and avoid the use of a sequential compactness argument.

$\partial U(w)$ is a $k$-dimensional sphere, and you correctly argue that it is compact by assumption (it is the union of upper and lower hemisphere which are homeomorphic to the closed ball in $\mathbb R^k$). Thus $\partial U(w)$ is covered by a finite subset $G_0$ of $G$. The union of the elements in $G_0$ is an open neighborhood $U$ of $\partial U(w)$. We wish to show that $U$ contains a spherical shell $S(w,\delta) = \{ x \in \mathbb R^{k+1} \mid w -\delta < \lVert x \rVert < w + \delta \}$. If we know this, we pick $l$ such that $w -\delta < l < w$. Then $U(l)$ is covered by a finite subset $G_l$ of $G$. The set $G' = G_0 \cup G_l$ is finite and covers $U(w+\delta)$ which contradicts the definition of $w$.

How to find $\delta$? Consider the homeomorphism $$h : \mathbb R^{k+1} \setminus \{0\} \to S^k \times (0,\infty), h(x) = \left(\frac{x}{\lVert x \rVert}, \lVert x \rVert\right)$$ whose inverse is given by $$h^{-1}(y,t) = ty.$$ Then $h(U)$ is an open neighborhood of $S^k \times \{w\}$. By the tube lemma there is $\delta > 0$ such that $V = S^k \times (w-\delta, w+\delta) \subset h(U)$. Then $h^{-1}(V) \subset U$ is the desired spherical shell $S(w,\delta)$.

$\endgroup$
3
  • $\begingroup$ I appreciate your answer, it is quite elegant to consider a homeomorphism into this "spherical space", but is it possible to generalise this to an arbitrary metric space? I prefer sequential compactness, since then one can adapt this proof to prove that a bounded, complete metric space is compact if and only if the boundary of every closed ball is compact. (If you have seen this before please let me know as well, I haven't been able to find it in the literature) $\endgroup$
    – Carlyle
    Commented Nov 13, 2023 at 9:06
  • $\begingroup$ @Carlyle No, my approach does not work in an arbitrary metric space. And the claim that a bounded, complete metric space is compact if and only if the boundary of every closed ball is compact is false. But comments are inadequate to discuss this. If you want, ask a new question. $\endgroup$
    – Paul Frost
    Commented Nov 13, 2023 at 9:35
  • $\begingroup$ thank you, I found a counterexample, so I will not ask a question anymore, it seems however that the claim will hold true for vector spaces, but I don't think that is too interesting of a result $\endgroup$
    – Carlyle
    Commented Nov 13, 2023 at 11:17

You must log in to answer this question.

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged .