8
$\begingroup$

So I'm taking real analysis and have noted that one of the benefits of the Dedekind cut is that 'if one of the sets made has an upper bound it also has a least upper bound'.

I don't understand how a set can have an upper bound and no least upper bound, though.

Is what can lead to this declaring a set in the rationals that is bounded above by an irrational number? I don't see any other way for this to be true (and I don't know why you'd ever make that set, or similarly why it's a 'special' property of the Dedekind cut rather than the general case).

Thank you for your time,

$\endgroup$
6
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ Try $\emptyset$ $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 28, 2015 at 17:04
  • $\begingroup$ Ever look at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Surreal_number ? $\endgroup$
    – JB King
    Commented Aug 28, 2015 at 17:12
  • $\begingroup$ RE Hagen: But doesn't that has no upper bound at all, rather than an upper bound and no least upper bound? $\endgroup$
    – liqiudilk
    Commented Aug 28, 2015 at 17:12
  • $\begingroup$ RE JB: Looking at it now. Haven't come across it before $\endgroup$
    – liqiudilk
    Commented Aug 28, 2015 at 17:13
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @liqiudilk $0$ is an upper bound of $\emptyset$ because every element of $\emptyset$ is less than $0$. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 28, 2015 at 17:14

3 Answers 3

5
$\begingroup$

$\sup S$ is shorthand for the least upper bound of $S$ in some set $T\supset S$ with respect to an order $\leq$ on $T$. However, we often omit $T$ and $\leq$ when they are obvious from the context.

Consider the case when $T=\mathbb{Q}$ and $\leq$ is the usual order. Since $\sup\left\{ x\in\mathbb{Q}:x^{2}<2\right\} $ has an upper bound but no least upper bound (in $T=\mathbb{Q}$), this supremum does not exist. Hence, $\mathbb{Q}$ does not satisfy the least upper bound property (a.k.a. Dedekind completeness).

However, if instead we had $T=\mathbb{R}$, the above supremum is $\sqrt{2}$.

Another example is given by @Hagen von Eitzen, where we look for $\sup \emptyset$. Regardless of whether $T=\mathbb{Q}$ or $T=\mathbb{R}$, in both of these spaces, $0$ is an upper bound of $\emptyset$. Furthermore, if $x$ is an upper bound of the empty set, so too is $x-1$. Therefore, there exists no least upper bound. We can write this as $\sup\emptyset = -\infty$ (in fact, if $T=\overline{\mathbb{R}}$, the extended reals with the obvious order, this is a precise statement).

Note that this does not contradict Dedekind completeness of the reals because Dedekind completeness only requires bounded nonempty sets to have supremums.

$\endgroup$
1
  • $\begingroup$ Ah - this makes sense. Thank you all very much! $\endgroup$
    – liqiudilk
    Commented Aug 28, 2015 at 17:16
1
$\begingroup$

The set $$\left\{\sum_{k=1}^n\frac1{k!}:n\in\Bbb N\right\}$$ is contained in the rationals, and has upper bound. It is not difficult to show that $3$ is an upper bound.

But in the reals, the series converges to $e$, which is not rational. For a relatively easy proof, see here.

$\endgroup$
0
$\begingroup$

Say we have a continuous function $f :\Bbb{Q}\to \Bbb{Q}$ for which we know $f(a)<0<f(b)$ for fixed rational numbers $a<b$. Now set

$$ M:=\{x\mid a\leq x\leq b \text{ and } f(x)<0\}. $$

Clearly,$M$ is bounded above. Suppose that $M$ has a least upper bound $\alpha$. It is not hard to see that this entails $f(\alpha)=0$ (if you don't believe it, I will add the proof).

Thus, if $f$ has no root in $a\leq x \leq b$, then $M$ cannot have a least upper bound (in $\Bbb{Q}$). This happens e.g. for $f(x)=x^2-2$. In this case, the set $M$ reduces to the case for which you write "I don't know why you would ever make such a set".

We have just seen te answer: Such a set pops up naturally if we want to prove the intermediate value theorem which is a very natural and useful theorem but which fails in general for noncomplete sets like $\Bbb{Q}$.

$\endgroup$

You must log in to answer this question.

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged .