51
$\begingroup$

Recently I have come across the equation

$$x^{x^{x^{x^{...}}}} = 2$$

which I found out to be solvable using substitution:

$$u = x^{x^{x^{x^{...}}}} = 2$$ $$x^u = 2$$ $$x^2 = 2$$ $$x = \sqrt{2}$$

Thinking about that, I tried to apply the same concept to other operations

$$ x \cdot x \cdot x \cdot x\space \cdot \space ...\space= 2 $$ $$u = x \cdot x \cdot x \cdot x\space \cdot \space ...\space= 2$$ $$x \cdot u = 2$$ $$2x = 2$$ $$x = 1$$

This solution is rather strange, as $1 \cdot 1 \cdot 1 ...$ should of course always equal $1$, but the equation says something else. Same thing goes for the addition:

$$x + x + x + x + \space ...\space= 2$$ $$u = x + x + x + \space...\space= 2$$ $$x + u = 2$$ $$x + 2 = 2$$ $$x = 0 $$

Which basically says that if you add $0$ up often enough you get $2$. And the next problem is, if you define the sum to equal $1$ instead of $2$ you end up with $1 = 2$. So obviously there must be a mistake here.

Is there any reason why this approach can be used for infinite powers but not sums and products?

$\endgroup$
5
  • 52
    $\begingroup$ If you assume a solution exists then you can find it or come upon a contradiction. If you come across a contradiction, that implies that one of your assumptions was incorrect, which in this case would be the assumption that a solution exists in the first place. $\endgroup$
    – JMoravitz
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:10
  • $\begingroup$ This reminds me of the non-measurable set example. A set $A$ is non-measurable if countably infinite copies of it constitute a set $B$ with finite measure. The set $A$ cannot have measure $0$, because otherwise the measure of $B$ would be $0$. Neither can $A$ have a positive measure, because otherwise the measure of $B$ would be infinite. $\endgroup$
    – Zhuoran He
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 20:15
  • 6
    $\begingroup$ Always suspect of infinity, weird things happen over there :-) Also "often enough" is very, very, really, really! very far from infinity. $\endgroup$ Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 22:05
  • $\begingroup$ I ran into a similar problem with continued fractions. The issue at heart is the same (i.e. the assumption that the sequence converges at all), so you might find the answers there to be useful as well. $\endgroup$ Commented Oct 19, 2017 at 9:46
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ @JMoravitz Why didn't you put that as an answer instead of a comment? Comments are not for answers, and you would have received 320 rep (at the time of writing this comment) :P $\endgroup$
    – Pedro A
    Commented Oct 19, 2017 at 23:06

5 Answers 5

58
$\begingroup$

The problem is when you make those kinds of substitutions you are assuming that the associated sequence is convergent. That is true for the first case but it is not for the second.

In the second case you have:

$$x\cdot x\cdot x ...=2$$

It is equivalent to

$$\lim_{n\to \infty}x^n=2$$

But if you have $|x|>1$ then we have two cases: if $x>1$ then the limit will be $\infty$ but if $x<-1$ then $x^n$ will oscillate for $+\infty$ or $-\infty$ and then we don't have limit is this case:

$$\lim_{n\to \infty}x^n=\infty \text{ or } \nexists \lim_{n\to \infty}x^n \quad (1)$$

which means that it is not convergent. Otherwise, if $|x|<1$ then

$$\lim_{n\to \infty}x^n=0 \quad (2)$$

For, if $x=1$ we get

$$\lim_{n\to \infty}x^n=1 \quad (3)$$

and, finally, for $x=-1$ we have that $x^n$ will oscillate. It will be $1$ when $n$ is even and $-1$ when $n$ is odd so $\lim_{n\to \infty}x^n$ doesn't exist. $(4)$

From $(1)$, $(2)$, $(3)$ and $(4)$ we conclude that you will never have

$$x\cdot x\cdot x ...=2$$

$\endgroup$
9
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ Thanks for the quick answer. When thinking about the problem I was already considering that the problem might be the convergence. However I dumped that thought immediately. After all, the concept of infinity his rather hard to grasp. After that explanation it seems pretty obvious to me though. $\endgroup$ Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:19
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ You'd need to handle the $|x|=1$ case too. $\endgroup$ Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:21
  • $\begingroup$ To add to this answer, here's a graph: imgur.com/GmucBJA . For each case, we can look at the loci of points such that $y=x+y,\;y=x\cdot y,\;y=x^y$. For $y=x+y$ (in red), the only place points that satisfy the equation are where $x=0$ (snore). For $y=x\cdot y$ (in black), the only points satisfy the equation have either $x=0$ or $x=1$ (still snore). But for $y=x^y$, we get a whole funky curve in green - all of these points are limits of the sequence $x^{x^{x^\ldots}}$. $\endgroup$
    – Jam
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:32
  • $\begingroup$ ^ I think I should correct my comment - some of the points on the graph (for $0<y<e$) are limits of the sequence. $\endgroup$
    – Jam
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:56
  • $\begingroup$ @HenningMakholm: Thanks. Updated. $\endgroup$
    – Arnaldo
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 20:19
23
$\begingroup$

There are three issues here.

You did it backwards

You have done what is basically the common high school algebra mistake of doing problems backwards — what you have proven is:

(Assuming that the product satisfies that algebraic identity) if $x$ is a real number solution to $x \cdot x \cdot x \cdot \ldots = 2$, then $x = 1$

In particular, you have completely forgotten to put any work towards showing

If $x=1$, then $x$ is a solution to $x \cdot x \cdot x \cdot \ldots = 2$

You haven't defined the problem

Multiplication is a binary operation. By induction, you can extend multiplication to any finite number of operands.

If you want to talk about multiplying infinitely many operands, then the above is insufficient. You have to find some way to make sense of such an operation.

You might do this by considering the "limit of partial products" approach from introductory calculus; e.g.

$$ x \cdot x \cdot x \cdot \ldots := \lim_{n \to \infty} \underbrace{x \cdot x \cdot \ldots \cdot x}_{n \text{ factors}} $$

You probably misunderstand infinitary operations

I infer this because you write as if:

  • Your product has a first factor
  • Your product has a last factor
  • Your product has infinitely many factors

While it is possible to arrange for such a thing, it is unusual and contrary to the common meaning of notation. One who actually understands how to arrange for this would understand the need to actually explain more precisely what they actually mean.

Thus, I imagine you either made a mistake (e.g. you did not mean to put a final term), or simply misunderstand infinitary algebra.

$\endgroup$
7
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ You are right, I don't know much about infinitary algebra. As I said, I found out about the infinite power equation and tried to use that knowledge to learn even more things. I have one question regarding your answer though, if it is not too complex for a comment: In the third part, you say, I write as if my product had a first factor. I do understand that there is no last factor, but why isn't there any first factor? $\endgroup$ Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:30
  • $\begingroup$ @zockDoc Infinity stretches in both directions, and we treat each end as the same point. See after the two series here. $\endgroup$
    – DonielF
    Commented Oct 19, 2017 at 14:03
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @zockDoc I disagree with DonielF and agree with you. It is completely OK for it to have a first factor. For Hurkyl's answer, although I can't speak for him, I believe that what he meant is that you can't normally have those three bullet points at the same time. But you can have a first factor if you don't have a last factor. Also, you could have a last factor if you don't have a first factor (as in a product from minus infinity to zero, for example). And you could have both if you have a finite amount of factors. "Infinity stretches in both directions" is incorrect in general. $\endgroup$
    – Pedro A
    Commented Oct 19, 2017 at 23:04
  • $\begingroup$ @Hamsteriffic - You are also making an assumption. Actually, you can have a first and last factor and infinitely many between them. The ordinals from $0$ to $\omega + 1$ is an example. What you can't have is (1) a first and last element (2) every other element has both an immediate predecessor and immediate successor and (3) an infinite number of elements. $\endgroup$ Commented Oct 20, 2017 at 3:46
  • $\begingroup$ @PaulSinclair I know that, hence I said "normally" (and Hurkyl also said it's possible). But I see that perhaps I could have been more precise in my comment. I just didn't want to insert this complicated stuff when I see that OP's question is about the simpler situation. Thanks :) $\endgroup$
    – Pedro A
    Commented Oct 20, 2017 at 8:40
19
$\begingroup$

Perhaps someone will chime in with a deeper reason, but let me explain "what you're doing" more formally. An infinite expression like $$ x^{x^{x^{x^\cdots}}} $$ is typically taken to mean the limit of the sequence $$ x, x^x, x^{x^x}, x^{x^{x^x}}, \ldots. $$ That is, the sequence $s$ is defined by $s_0 = x$ and $s_{n+1} = x^{s_n}$; and the number we are looking for is the limit of this sequence, if it exists. Now note that the operation $r \mapsto x^r$ is continuous for positive $r$ (let's say that $x$ is also positive), and thus we have that $$ \lim_{n \to \infty} s_n = \lim_{n \to \infty} s_{n+1} = \lim_{n \to \infty} x^{s_n} = x^{\lim_{n \to \infty} s_n}. $$ Now, solving this equation is what gave you $x = \sqrt 2$. Thus, this tells you that if the sequence converges, then $x = \sqrt 2$.

In the other examples, you know the same thing. However, because you don't know if the sequences converge (and in fact you can easily check that they don't) the knowledge is vacuous.

$\endgroup$
2
  • 6
    $\begingroup$ That proviso "if the sequence converges" is needed. If the 2 in the OP's equation is replaced by 4, that gives $x^4=4$, yielding $x=\sqrt{2}$ again! (Supposing that a real $x>0$ is required.) If $x=\sqrt{2}$, $x^{x^{x^{\dots}}}$ can't possibly be both 2 and 4. $\endgroup$
    – Rosie F
    Commented Oct 19, 2017 at 11:16
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ +1 for actually going into why the approach works for the power tower case. $\endgroup$
    – R.M.
    Commented Oct 20, 2017 at 16:02
1
$\begingroup$

Well, convergence issues. You have to carefully define what your infinite power is and check for convergence. Your method only works if we indeed have a convergent sequence.

$\endgroup$
1
$\begingroup$

The problem is in the convergence. you can only get an value of a function if it convergences. Look at $x\times x\times x\times\cdots$: $$x\times x\times x\times\cdots=\lim_{n\to\infty}x^n=\begin{cases}\infty & |x|>1\\0 & |x|<1\end{cases}$$ so the equation $x\times x\times x\times\cdots=2\,$ has no answer $$$$and for $x+x+x+\cdots$: $$x+x+x+\cdots=\lim_{n\to\infty}nx=\begin{cases}\infty&x>0\\0&x=0\\-\infty&x<0\end{cases}$$so $x+x+x+\cdots=2$ also has no answer

$\endgroup$
5
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ Why would the second limit be "indeterminate" for $x=0$? The limit of the sequence $0,0,0,\ldots$ is obviously $0$. $\endgroup$ Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:20
  • $\begingroup$ if $0\times n=0$ and $\infty\times n=\infty$ then how can you know what $0\times \infty$ is? you can get a result only if there are $2$ functions that $f(x_0)=0,g(x_0)=\infty$ so $$\lim_{x\to x_0}f(x)g(x)$$ because $f(x)g(x)=\frac{1}{\frac{1}{f(x)}}g(x)=\frac{g(x)}{\frac{1}{f(x)}}$ and when you take the limit you will get $\frac{\infty}{\infty}$ and you can solve that limit, but here you have $0\times\infty$ without any way to get the limit $\endgroup$
    – Holo
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:27
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ @Holo Limits (as $x\to c$) aren't substitutions of $c$ in place of $x$; they're what happens to sequences when $x$ gets near $c$. Clearly you can't substitute $\infty$ in place of $x$ so Henning's point is that the sequence $n\cdot x$ for $n=1,2,3,4,\ldots$ and $x=0$ is the sequence $(0\cdot 1), (0\cdot 2), (0\cdot 3), \ldots$, which is $0,0,0\ldots$. Clearly no matter how many terms you've got, the elements of the sequence are still $0$ (so the limit is definitely not indeterminate) - we're not finding $0\times \infty$, we're just showing what the sequence approaches :) $\endgroup$
    – Jam
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:37
  • $\begingroup$ @Jam oh, okay i changed it, btw, what is the behavior of $x\times x\times x\cdots$ at $x=-1$? $\endgroup$
    – Holo
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:43
  • $\begingroup$ @Holo Oscillates between $1$ and $-1$ (so it's not got a limit) $\endgroup$
    – Jam
    Commented Oct 18, 2017 at 19:45

You must log in to answer this question.

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged .