8
$\begingroup$

A quandle $(Q,\triangleleft,\triangleleft^{-1})$ is a set $Q$ with two binary operations $\triangleleft,\triangleleft^{-1}:Q\times Q\to Q$ such that the following hold for all $x,y,z\in Q$:

(Q1) Idempotency: $x\triangleleft x=x$.

(Q2) Right-invertibility: $(x\triangleleft y)\triangleleft^{-1}y=x=(x\triangleleft^{-1}y)\triangleleft y$.

(Q3) Right-distributivity: $(x\triangleleft y)\triangleleft z=(x\triangleleft z)\triangleleft(y\triangleleft z)$.

These axioms may seem somewhat arbitrary, but I claim they aren't: They correspond to the Reidemeister moves in knot theory. Moreover, if $G$ is a group, then defining the operation $x\triangleleft y=y^{-1}xy$ on $G$ gives a quandle structure, and as shown by Joyce in 1982, these three axioms are sufficient to capture the equational content of conjugation.

A profinite quandle is an inverse limit $\varprojlim_{\lambda\in\Lambda}Q_\lambda$ of an inverse system of finite quandles. Those familiar with the theory of profinite groups will recognize this construction.

It is known for profinite groups the following result: Every profinite group can be endowed with a Stone topology, i.e., compact, Hausdorff, and totally disconnected. On the other hand, every Stone-topological group is profinite. This result can be found in Johnstone's book on Stone spaces, though it is presented in much more generality such that any finitary algebraic category with a "complete word set" in some variable admits this Stone-topological/profinite equivalence. Johnstone also gives sufficient requirements for having a complete word set. However, one of these requirements (distributivity) is not met by quandles.

Is there reason to believe that quandles admit such an equivalence? Perhaps there is some reason to believe this in relation to quandles characterizing group conjugation, but I haven't been able to work it out. I know there is a direct proof for Stone-topological groups being profinite, see my previous question. However, this relies on having an identity element, which quandles don't have. Any insight would be appreciated.

$\endgroup$
8
  • $\begingroup$ The usual way to prove these things is to start with a clopen equivalence relation on your space and take the largest congruence contained in that equivalence relation and prove the congruence is clopen. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 27, 2023 at 17:16
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @BenjaminSteinberg Would you be able to explain how working with clopen congruences in this way implies that the object is profinite? This sort of reasoning was mentioned to me in the past, but I didn't understand it. Thank you for investing time on my question. $\endgroup$
    – Alex Byard
    Commented Aug 27, 2023 at 22:27
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ You can find it in section 3.1 of my book the q-theory of finite semigroups with John Rhodes. I'm not sure if that is the most readable presentation. The original proof is ams.org/journals/proc/1957-008-04/S0002-9939-1957-0087032-5 but it is written with very old fashioned terminology so it is not very readable, $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 28, 2023 at 11:24
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ What kind of distributivity (over which operation) is not met by quandles while it should be? $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 28, 2023 at 18:27
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @MaartenHavinga Well, one issue is associativity: $x\triangleleft(y\triangleleft z)\neq(x\triangleleft y)\triangleleft z$. When phrased as a first order theory, there isn't an issue with distributivity. This is because you don't have to worry about a total ordering of the binary operations: There's only one of them. $\endgroup$
    – Alex Byard
    Commented Aug 29, 2023 at 20:42

1 Answer 1

2
$\begingroup$

Here is how the proof works for monoids. This doesn't really answer the question so I made this communitywiki, but maybe the OP will find it useful.

Let $X$ be a compact Hausdorff space. Call an equivalence relation $R$ on $X$ open if it has open equivalence classes. By compactness, an open equivalence relation $R$ has finitely many classes and $X/R$ is a finite discrete space. Notice that the intersection of two open equivalence relations is open.

Note that a compact Hausdorff space is totally disconnected if and only if the intersection of all the open equivalence relations (in $X\times X$) is the diagonal. Moreover, $X\cong \varprojlim X/R$ where $R$ is any cofinal set downward directed set of open equivalence relations.

Numakura's Theorem: Let $M$ be a compact and totally disconnected topological monoid (the monoid is done just to make the congruence slightly less complicated to describe). Then $M$ is profinite.

Proof. It suffices by the above discussion to show that if $R$ is an open equivalence relation on $M$ then there is an open congruence contained in $R$ (note the open congruences are closed under intersection and hence downward directed).

Define $\sim$ by $m\sim n$ iff $umv\mathrel{R} unv$ for all $u,v\in M$ (for semigroups, one has to adjust to compensate for not having the possibility $u,v$ are the identity).

It is an easy exercise to verify that $\sim$ is a congruence contained in $R$. We claim it is open. If $m\in M$, then the $\sim$-class of $m$ can be described as $\bigcap_{Y\in M/R}(\bigcup_{u,v\in M,umv\in Y}u^{-1}Yv^{-1})$ where $u^{-1} Yv^{-1} =\{n\in M\mid unv\in Y\}$. Since each $Y\in M/R$ is open and multiplication is continuous, $u^{-1}Yv^{-1}$ is open. Since $M/R$ is finite, we conclude that the $\sim$-class of $m$ is open.

$\endgroup$

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged or ask your own question.