100
$\begingroup$

In mathematics, is there any conjecture about the existence of an object that was proven to exist but that has not been explicitly constructed to this day? Here object could be any mathematical object, such as a number, function, algorithm, or even proof.

$\endgroup$
13

11 Answers 11

112
$\begingroup$

It is known that there is an even integer $n\le246$ such that there are infinitely many primes $p$ such that the next prime is $p+n$, but there is no specific $n$ which has been proved to work (although everyone believes that every even $n\ge2$ actually works).

$\endgroup$
15
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ Is this similar to the twin primes conjecture? $\endgroup$
    – jkd
    Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 22:20
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ You can state it three ways: There are infinitely many primes that are at most 246 apart (at most 2 would be twin primes). There is an integer n ≤ 246 such that infinitely many primes are exactly n apart (n = 246 would be twin primes). Of the twin prime conjecture, (n,n+4) prime conjecture, ..., (n, n+246) conjecture, at least one is true. $\endgroup$
    – gnasher729
    Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 22:55
  • 6
    $\begingroup$ @jkd, if we could get that 246 down to 2, we'd have the twin prime conjecture. This is as close as anyone has been able to get to it. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 16, 2018 at 4:37
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ It has been proven that there exists an $n \leq 246$, but has it been proven that this is provable for a specific $n$? $\endgroup$
    – JiK
    Commented Aug 16, 2018 at 13:01
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ @JiK I had the same concern, until I read the actual question post, not just the title. "is there any conjecture about the existence of an object that was proven to exist but that has not been explicitly constructed to this day?" We know such an $n$ exists, and that it is smaller than $246$, but we haven't explicitly constructed such a number. $\endgroup$
    – Arthur
    Commented Aug 17, 2018 at 10:55
48
$\begingroup$

I am not sure this answers your question but it seems to come close. The Wikipedia article Skewes number states

In number theory, Skewes's number is any of several extremely large numbers used by the South African mathematician Stanley Skewes as upper bounds for the smallest natural number $x$ for which $\, \pi(x) > \textrm{li}(x) \,$ where $\pi$ is the prime-counting function and $\, \textrm{li} \,$ is the logarithmic integral function.

It further states that

All numerical evidence then available seemed to suggest that $\, \pi(x) \,$ was always less than $\, \textrm{li}(x). \,$ Littlewood's proof did not, however, exhibit a concrete such number $x$.

The problem is that even though the existence of the number $x$ has been proven, we only know huge upper bounds on the first such number.

Perhaps a better example is from the Wikipedia article Ramsey theory where

Problems in Ramsey theory typically ask a question of the form: "how many elements of some structure must there be to guarantee that a particular property will hold?"

These Ramsey numbers have the property that

Results in Ramsey theory typically have two primary characteristics. Firstly, they are non-constructive: they may show that some structure exists, but they give no process for finding this structure (other than brute-force search). For instance, the pigeonhole principle is of this form. Secondly, while Ramsey theory results do say that sufficiently large objects must necessarily contain a given structure, often the proof of these results requires these objects to be enormously large – bounds that grow exponentially, or even as fast as the Ackermann function are not uncommon.

Thus, in theory, some of these enumerative numbers exist but they are too huge to write explicitly. In other cases, there exist small bounds but it is very hard to narrow the bounds.

$\endgroup$
3
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ See also the idea of the minimax value or "God's Number" for combinatorial problems like puzzle games. Often the exact value is not known, but an upper bound is. E.g. until 2010 is was not known that the maximum number of steps to solve any Rubik's Cube is 20; the first known upper bound for this value was 277. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Optimal_solutions_for_Rubik%27s_Cube $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 12, 2018 at 23:27
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ Actually, Ramsay numbers aren't that big. For instance, $40<R_5<50$, but still exact value is unknown. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 10:08
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ @m69: Yep. In general, finding the minimum natural number that satisfies some complicated computable property (after proving non-constructively that one exists) is explicitly solvable but whose solution might take a long time to find, especially if the property has combinatorial explosion. The minimum number of moves to solve a 3x3x3 Rubik's cube is known today, but surely we will never find the minimum number of moves to solve a 7x7x7 Rubik's cube! $\endgroup$
    – user21820
    Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 10:18
43
$\begingroup$

It's known that no matter the size of the board, the first player has a winning strategy in Chomp, but an explicit winning strategy is only known for smallish boards.

$\endgroup$
2
  • 22
    $\begingroup$ One can apply Zermelo's theorem to chess, Go, and other finite games. They are all determined, but we don't know who has the winning strategy (or at least, non-losing one) $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 10:13
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ or any other ultra-weak-ly solved game en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Solved_game $\endgroup$
    – Charon ME
    Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 6:42
34
$\begingroup$

Well, this might be an example of what you are asking for:

Take the question "are there irrational numbers $a,b$ such that $a^b$ is rational?"

A quick way to see that there are is to consider $\alpha =\sqrt 2^ {\sqrt 2}$.

Either $\alpha$ is rational or irrational. If it is rational, then we are done. If it is irrational then consider $\alpha^{\sqrt 2}=2$. Either way, we can find an example.

To be sure, it is possible (though quite difficult) to show that $\alpha$ is irrational and there are other ways to get direct examples (such as $e^{\ln 2}$) that settle the problem . But this indirect proof is so simple it is, I think, worth study.

$\endgroup$
4
  • 16
    $\begingroup$ The status of $\sqrt 2^ {\sqrt 2}$ is known: it is irrational. $\endgroup$
    – lhf
    Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 16:21
  • 12
    $\begingroup$ @lhf Yes, I pointed that out in my post. Still though, the simplicity of this argument has always appealed to me. Even an expression like $e^{\ln 2}$ needs hard work...unless I am missing something, you need the transcendence of $e$ to show that $\ln 2 $ is irrational. (though I suppose an example like $(\sqrt 3)^{\log_{3} 4}=2$ is simple enough). $\endgroup$
    – lulu
    Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 16:32
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ I think a better example would be that at least one of e+pi and e*pi is irrational, since it's not yet known which is irrational, or if both are. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 19:32
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @BallpointBen Ok, though both underlying theorems there ("there exist irrationals whose sum is irrational, and there exist irrationals whose product is irrational") are extremely easy to prove. $\endgroup$
    – lulu
    Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 19:44
34
$\begingroup$

Define the following number:

$$K = \begin{cases} 1, & \text{if Riemann Hypothesis is true} \\ 0, & \text{if it is false} \end{cases}$$

Since the Riemann Hypothesis is either true or false, the above constant $K$ is well-defined, mathematically. It is one specific number. But no one knows whether it is 0 or 1 (because knowing it means knowing the answer to the hypothesis).

I know this example is very artificial, but nevertheless I thought it was interesting to share - basically any unsolved problem in mathematics can be converted in an object that certainly exists but knowing what it is becomes equivalent to solving the problem itself in the first place.

$\endgroup$
7
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ Though many of us, and a few computer programs, assume $K = 1$. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 4:38
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ Is this correct? Can we say any hypothesis is true? Isn't the correct wording "can be proven within an axiom system"? And if that's so, what if it is like the continuum hypothesis? $\endgroup$
    – chx
    Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 19:44
  • 47
    $\begingroup$ This fails the "the problem was proved to be solvable" requirement. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 20:06
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ @Solomonoff'sSecret: Trivially fixable. Given the definition of K, consider K*K = K. Obviously true, but we don't know whether the proof is 1*1=1 or 0*0=0. $\endgroup$
    – MSalters
    Commented Aug 14, 2018 at 15:21
  • 6
    $\begingroup$ @MSalters I think that still doesn't qualify. You give a certain positive proof that $K^2 = K$, not a proof that something or its negation can be proven without knowing which. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 14, 2018 at 16:25
15
$\begingroup$

There are sentences, called Parikh sentences for which there are short proofs that the sentence is provable but all proofs are very long. My discussion is based on page 17 of Noson Yanofsky's arXiv article A Universal Approach to Self-Referential Paradoxes, Incompleteness and Fixed Points. He constructs a sentence $\mathcal{C}_{n}$ that says, "I do not have a proof of myself that is shorter than $n$. Then choose a large $n$, say $P!$, where $P$ is a reasonable estimate of the number of electrons in the observable universe.

In the above article Yanofsky states his discussion is based on R. Parikh's Existence and Feasiblity in Arithmetic.

$\endgroup$
3
  • $\begingroup$ But there is an algorithm to construct this sentence, right? Just try all natural numbers until you find the correct one. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 12, 2018 at 23:38
  • $\begingroup$ @Federico Poloni -- Yes, the paper provides a description of the sentence $\endgroup$
    – Jay
    Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 14:40
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ Where does the quoted sentence end? (Or is it intended that all subsequent text, including this comment, is part of the sentence?) $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 14, 2018 at 16:21
13
$\begingroup$

Not every mathematical object can be explicitly constructed. For example, there are uncountably many real numbers, but only countably many finite strings in a given finite alphabet (let's say ASCII). An explicit construction of a real number is a finite ASCII string, and by definition it can only construct at most one real number, so that leaves uncountably many real numbers that can't be explicitly constructed.

$\endgroup$
9
  • $\begingroup$ Who said explicit constructions had to be finite? $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 2:19
  • 6
    $\begingroup$ If it's infinite, you can't read all of it. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 3:15
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ How do you reconcile this with models of set theory where every set is definable (including every real number)? $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 9:23
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @AsafKaragila you don't, that's the point: such models are “unrealistic” in the sense that not every set they call “definable” could actually be specified by a human. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 14:22
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ Robert, I'm not entirely sure what you mean. Yes, these models are countable, but it just might be that the universe of mathematics [that you are working in, if you prefer to avoid Platonism,] is such model (of course, we have no way of proving something like that, but the point is that there is no way of disproving it either). $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Commented Aug 13, 2018 at 18:16
10
$\begingroup$

One could say that for many problems that are NP hard, it is often known that the solution exists, but (in many cases) we don't have the computational power to evaluate it exactly, so we use algorithms that we hope are close to the optimal solution.

Probably one of the most commonly known NP hard problems is the traveling salesman. In this problem, we want to find the shortest route connecting a set of nodes. Clearly, a solution does exist; in fact, it's really easy to consider a finite set of candidate solutions, one of which must have the shortest route.

The problem is that generally speaking, this finite set we need to consider is still very large, and we must evaluate the length on the routes for each element in these sets to obtain the answer. Simplistic approaches result in a set of size $O(n!)$. Reading through the wikipedia page on the problem, it seems that there are methods that reduce this to $O(n^2 2^n)$. Note that this means the human race does not have enough computational power to solve this problem for a couple hundred nodes within our lifetime [citation needed].

But a solution must exist!

$\endgroup$
5
  • $\begingroup$ yes, pointing to the NP hard class is a really good hint. And there are many other problems. NP complete problems fit in too, like the Clique, Map Colorability and Packing problems. We know there is a solution, we are just not able to find it yet. All we have are approximation algorithms (which I dont like because they are not exact) $\endgroup$
    – undefined
    Commented Aug 14, 2018 at 11:08
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ As a computer scientist I would say we do know how to solve TSP, it just takes a huge amount of time to do so exhaustively. Thus the "direct solution" mentioned in the title is known, although very impractical. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 14, 2018 at 21:41
  • $\begingroup$ @AndreaLazzarotto do you have a link or something to a working (solution) algorithm for TSP? $\endgroup$
    – undefined
    Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 6:39
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ @undefined, every instance of TSP is a finite problem, so, in principle, you can just look at every single one of the possible paths through all the points, and pick out the shortest one. That's a guaranteed-to-work algorithm for TSP. It's just a tiny bit slow, that's all. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 7:23
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ @undefined, enumerate all possible solutions, compute their weight, chose the best one. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 10:12
7
$\begingroup$

Maybe the Picard–Lindelöf theorem is what you are looking for. It is an existence theorem for solutions of differential equations and it uses the Banach fixed point theorem. It basically says, under certain conditions differential equations have a unique solution. But to find the solution for any given differential equation is rather hard (and not alway possible).

$\endgroup$
3
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ What do you mean by "find the solution"? The solution is a certain function, which can be approximated to arbitrary accuracy by numerical methods. It might not have a "closed form" expression, though. Well, not all functions have closed form expressions, just as not all real numbers are rational. $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 14, 2018 at 15:32
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @RobertIsrael True. Do you know if there is a full classification of differential equations if they have closed form solution or dont admit one. How would you interpret the original question instead? $\endgroup$
    – lalala
    Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 10:34
  • $\begingroup$ "Closed form" is not precisely defined. There are algorithms in some cases, e.g. Kovacic's for determining whether a second-order linear homogeneous d.e. with rational coefficients has Liouvillian solutions, but AFAIK there is no "full classification". $\endgroup$ Commented Aug 15, 2018 at 15:59
6
$\begingroup$

It is known that the game of Hex cannot end in a draw (visually this makes sense, either there is a path side to side or up and down). This implies that the first player has a winning strategy since the first player can always 'steal' the second player's strategy. However, an explicit strategy is only known for very small boards.

$\endgroup$
1
  • $\begingroup$ But this assumes that the first player knows what strategy the second player picked, which is not true? $\endgroup$
    – Dymista
    Commented Nov 30, 2023 at 22:48
5
$\begingroup$

stackzebra posted an answer, which has been deleted by a moderator. It's a very simple answer, but, I think, a good one, so I'm going to post it (in a modified form) here:

It has been proved that there is a prime greater than $10^{10^{100}}$ – indeed, Euclid proved that there are infinitely many such primes – but no example has ever been given. The largest known primes are as infinitesimals compared to this number.

$\endgroup$
1
  • $\begingroup$ Indeed, if $n=10^{10^{100}}$, it has been proved that there is a prime between $n$ and $2n$, and of course it's just a finite computation to find one, but no one has ever carried out that computation. $\endgroup$ Commented Dec 8, 2019 at 23:05

You must log in to answer this question.

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged .