78
$\begingroup$

I am writing a blog post related to problem solving and one of the main techniques used in problem solving is drawing a diagram. Essentially, I want to illustrate that some hard problems (for example, word problems) can be done fairly easily when diagrams are drawn.

There is a paper related to this question but the problems in that paper are much to simple. I was considering using the problem statement of the Langley's Problem but that question is not too easy even after the diagram.

Does anyone have any ideas?

Thanks a lot!

EDIT:

As pointed out in the comments, it's difficult to define an "easy" problem or a "difficult" problem. So, I would like to add that the best examples would be within the undergraduate mathematics range or word problems that non-math majors/mathematicians would understand.

EDIT 2:

I would like to clarify further (thanks to @ruakh) that "when a person trying to solve the problem draws a diagram" is what I am looking for as opposed to "when a person who already knows the solution draws a diagram that illustrates it"

$\endgroup$
20
  • 48
    $\begingroup$ All of them. And I'm serious. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 12, 2015 at 12:20
  • 32
    $\begingroup$ None of them. And I'm just as serious. $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Commented Jan 12, 2015 at 15:26
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ @Ennar: I avoid algebra and categories like the plague. Those diagrams are never easy for me. I am working with supremely abstract and layered constructions in set theory (and with the absence of choice to aid me, those structures can't be reduced to ordinals, and they have no natural order on them), and the way I do it is to write the definitions, draw lines on a paper, and play plenty of Street Fighter Alpha 2 (and 3). $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 14:40
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ @Eric: I mean, when you think about a function from $\Bbb R$ to $\Bbb R$, you think about a nice continuous function, which is probably differentiable almost everywhere. But those functions are pathological. Most functions are not continuous or even close to being continuous. Even amongst continuous functions differentiable functions are just a meager subset, making them again the pathological ones. So when you draw an arbitrary function, how do you draw it? I just don't draw. $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 1:30
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ Some of them. And I'm sometimes just as serious. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 16, 2015 at 20:53

23 Answers 23

122
$\begingroup$

Question: Choose two points uniformly at random on the unit interval. What is the probability that these points are within distance $\frac{1}{2}$ of each other?

Solution:

The following picture is the set of points $(x,y)$ such that $|x−y|\leq\dfrac{1}{2}$:

Soltuion

So the probability is $\dfrac{3}{4}$.

$\endgroup$
1
  • $\begingroup$ I've even hit a classroom case where this sort of thing made it obvious. A guy was stumped on a homework problem sort of like this, I told him to draw it and the answer would be obvious. I forget the details by now, though. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 17, 2015 at 3:22
67
$\begingroup$

There's a triangle on top of a rectangle, in the following configuration. How much of the rectangle is covered?

triangle covering rectangle

I can't remember where I first heard this problem, but they had taken it to the streets. Almost everyone got it wrong, with 2/3 a popular answer. But when you draw a single vertical line you see it can be decomposed in two parts, each one half covered:

diagram solution

The solution is thus exactly 50%.

$\endgroup$
10
  • 11
    $\begingroup$ Ah, this is nice example, that is how you prove formula for area of triangle, which should be taught in elementary school. At least I do. But the popular answer, sadly, once again shows how poor mathematics education in general is. $\endgroup$
    – Ennar
    Commented Jan 13, 2015 at 12:47
  • 6
    $\begingroup$ Mind-boggling how that red line glaringly solves the problem. Whoever thought of that is a pure genius. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 20:00
  • 8
    $\begingroup$ @DanielV: That is begging the question. You only know the location of the top corner doesn't matter because you already know the area of the triangle. $\endgroup$
    – TonyK
    Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 0:15
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ @TonyK I was trying to suggest that due to the fact that the asker didn't specify where the top corner is, you could "cheat" and assume that it doesn't matter. Sort of like the "obviously this number is composite, because if it was prime, you wouldn't be asking me on a test" response. $\endgroup$
    – DanielV
    Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 0:52
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ I love this. Its the same example used in Lockhart's Lament. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 5:21
67
$\begingroup$

As an introduction to infinite series convergence:

$$\sum_{n=1}^\infty \frac1{2^n}$$

The fact that this sum converges to $1$ can be easily understood with this diagram (from Wikipedia):

geometric serie

$\endgroup$
1
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ This is even easier in one dimension! $\endgroup$ Commented Dec 6, 2016 at 23:55
48
$\begingroup$
  1. Almost all physics problems on forces and motion, free-body diagrams are go-to tools. enter image description here

  2. The Sieve of Eratosthenes makes it straightforward to find all primes less than a fixed number.

enter image description here

  1. Pascal's triangle for finding coefficients of a binomial expansion

  2. Many probability problems, interpreting probability as an area. For example, the probability of a dart hitting a particular geometric region on the board.

$\endgroup$
0
27
$\begingroup$

Perhaps this is too simple to include, but I find this example very appealing when speaking to non-math majors:

\begin{align*} 1 & = 1 \\ 1 + 2 + 1 & = 4 \\ 1 + 2 + 3 + 2 + 1 & = 9 \\ 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 3 + 2 + 1 & = 16 \\ & \vdots \end{align*}

and, in general, you might conjecture that $$ n^{2} = n + 2\sum_{k=1}^{n-1} k $$ For many people who know a bit of algebra, especially Gauss' famous childhood exploits, a bit of fiddling around will easily prove this, but the picture really makes you 'see' the formula:

enter image description here

And now anyone who can't see it yet, you show them this:

enter image description here

$\endgroup$
5
  • $\begingroup$ Should the upper index be $n-1$? $\endgroup$
    – GFauxPas
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 22:06
  • $\begingroup$ Yes of course, thank you. Edited. $\endgroup$
    – Shai
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 22:07
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ I don't get it. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 6:20
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @QuinnCulver: Count the points on each (northwest-to-southeast) diagonal. $\endgroup$
    – anomaly
    Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 17:09
  • $\begingroup$ A similar approach shows that the sum of the natural numbers from 1 to n is $(n^2 + n)/2$. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 17, 2015 at 8:35
22
$\begingroup$

When dealing with the countability of $\mathbb Z$ and $\mathbb Q$, this diagram of the Cantor pairing function assists greatly in understanding how they have the same cardinality as $\mathbb N$.


enter image description here

$\endgroup$
5
  • 11
    $\begingroup$ I never understood that diagram. But when the function was written and the proof was given, it was clear as the sky in the Sahara on a warm August day. $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Commented Jan 12, 2015 at 15:25
  • 6
    $\begingroup$ I personally found it helpful when I was first learning set theory to see that there indeed existed a one-to-one correspondence between the rationals and the natural numbers. $\endgroup$
    – Derek W
    Commented Jan 12, 2015 at 15:46
  • 9
    $\begingroup$ @AsafKaragila Really? To me, it is evidently clear that this diagram defines a "path" traversing all of $\mathbb{N} \times \mathbb{N}$. Do you mind if I ask where the conceptual difficulty lies for you? $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 12, 2015 at 22:42
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ @David: I find it hard to explain, since it's been so many years since I learned to "read" this drawing. Perhaps by the (correct) indoctrination that a drawing does not constitute a proof, and it's completely unclear to me how this sketch should continue (I mean, it was, now it's clear). So either you prove that such map exists without specifying it; or you actually write down the function and then you can just prove that it is a bijection, in which case all is clear again. It's hard to explain what's unclear about drawing, though. They just confuse me usually. $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Commented Jan 12, 2015 at 22:46
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ There are helpful drawings of Cantor's pairing function. This is not one of them. $\endgroup$
    – Raphael
    Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 9:04
22
$\begingroup$

Quoting Wikipedia:

There is a game that is isomorphic to tic-tac-toe, but on the surface appears completely different. Two players in turn say a number between one and nine. A particular number may not be repeated. The game is won by the player who has said three numbers whose sum is 15. Plotting these numbers on a 3×3 magic square shows that the game exactly corresponds with tic-tac-toe, since three numbers will be arranged in a straight line if and only if they total 15.

This is not exactly what the OP might have had in mind, since tic-tac-toe may not be easy, but it's well-known. OTOH, as John von Neumann said, "in mathematics you don't understand things, you just get used to them". So reducing to something well-known might not be that far from reducing to something easy.

$\endgroup$
4
  • $\begingroup$ That is an interesting one. As the game you describe would be rather annoying to play and keep track of. However the essentially identical visually represented game of tic-tac-toe is trivial to learn and play. $\endgroup$
    – zeel
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 18:51
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ Unless I'm missing something, the "only if" direction is quite nonobvious. $\endgroup$
    – user856
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 20:03
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ @Rahul: you're right, it is not obvious, but nevertheless true (for the classical 3x3 magic square). Edit: oops, the other way round: it's the "if" part which is nonobvious! $\endgroup$
    – mbork
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 20:40
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ Both are nonobvious - based on the empirical evidence above! If one were obvious, it could be trivially recognized as obvious, obviously. Therefore, there could not be any confusion which one is which - but there was confusion. :) $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 22, 2015 at 6:50
20
$\begingroup$

Here's one with Set Theory and a Venn Diagram. $$ $$ $$A-(B-C) = (A-B) \cup (A \cap B \cap C)$$ $$ $$

enter image description here

There are a lot of possible set relations that can be made simple with a diagram.

$\endgroup$
17
$\begingroup$

The snake lemma would be much more difficult to prove without a diagram: enter image description here

Picture from Wikipedia.

$\endgroup$
2
  • 6
    $\begingroup$ This is just the tip of the iceberg in terms of proofs in category theory which use commutative diagrams as the primary tool in the proof, almost an entire genre of proof called diagram chasing. See also the five lemma for an example. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 12, 2015 at 21:41
  • $\begingroup$ @MarioCarneiro: Yes I agree. I remember when I had to prove that the Bockstein operator and the rand operator anti-commutes. Without a huge 3-dim diagram that showed what was going on, it would have been impossible for me. $\endgroup$
    – Lehs
    Commented Jan 13, 2015 at 5:40
17
$\begingroup$

I find Kelly's proof of Sylvester-Gallai theorem absolutely marvelous.

Theorem: Given a finite set $S$ of non-collinear points in the plane, there is a line passing through exactly two of them. In other words, it is not possible to construct a set where every line passing through a pair of points will contain at least one more point from the set.

Proof: Suppose the contrary. Consider the set $L$ of all lines passing through at least three points of $S$. Choose a pair $(P\in S,\ell\in L)$ with minimal positive distance between $P$ and $\ell$, and then draw the picture (perpendicular from $P$ to $\ell$).

enter image description here

$\endgroup$
3
  • $\begingroup$ Why would the pair $(P, \ell)$ be unique? In fact, since for any $\ell\in L$, there is a point $P\in S$ on it (and thus having distance zero from it), just pick any $\ell \in L$ and any $P$ on it and you have an optimal pair. What am I misunderstanding? $\endgroup$
    – Jack M
    Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 0:21
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ @JackM As for the second point, "positive" meant "strictly greater than zero". If such a pair is not unique, it suffices to choose any of them. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 12:33
  • $\begingroup$ @HagenvonEitzen Yes, thanks! I corrected that. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 17, 2015 at 18:18
16
$\begingroup$

You are climbing up a mountain. Then you stop at the top to sleep. Then, in the morning, you climb down the mountain. Prove that there is a certain time at which your position on the first climb is the same as your position on the second climb.

Of course you can easily prove this without a diagram but to think of solving it this way for most people and most books uses a diagram used as an informal precursor to the solution I have in mind.

$\endgroup$
3
  • 28
    $\begingroup$ What kind of one-dimensional mountains are you climbing? $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 12, 2015 at 21:37
  • 2
    $\begingroup$ One with a trial that he follows. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 13, 2015 at 15:31
  • 3
    $\begingroup$ Can you post the diagram? $\endgroup$
    – Navin
    Commented Jan 27, 2015 at 10:52
11
$\begingroup$

Well, I'd say proof of Pythagoras theorem in Euclidean plane is elementary but important example where diagrams help a lot. Wikipedia article offers some of the possibilities.

$\endgroup$
11
$\begingroup$

Bayesian Networks have vastly simplified reasoning about complex conditional probability chains. You can illustrate this with an arbitrary example, but one of the classic ones is the "Earthquake" problem.

You're on vacation and have an alarm. If it goes off, it was either because a burglar broke into your house or an earthquake shook it hard enough to set it off. When your alarm goes off there's a chance that your neighbor John or your neighbor Mary may call.

From here, it's pretty freeform, you can reason about conditional (in)dependence given certain information (John calling is conditionally independent of Mary calling given info about whether the alarm went off for instance), or even relatively simply compute the joint distribution of certain nodes just by knowing things like the parents of each node.

There are very simple rules for determining conditional independence and calculating the actual joint probability tables of all of this if you draw this as a Bayes Net.

Obviously, a full intro to the specifics of Bayes Nets is outside the scope of this post, but the basic rules are widely available online or in the book Probabilistic Graphical Models.

enter image description here

A lecture can be found with the probability tables for and an outline working through this specific example here, though you can obviously make up any reasonable sounding set of tables on the fly.

$\endgroup$
11
$\begingroup$

Any sample problem for Bayes' Theorem. (Pic "stolen" from the Wikipedia article.)

enter image description here


One somewhat morbid formulation of the problem I remember would be:

  • $A$ = you have cancer
  • $\overline A$ = you do not have cancer
  • $B$ = the test for cancer came back positive
  • $\overline B$ = the test for cancer came back negative

Given that:

  1. the cancer is present in $0.5\%$ of the population
  2. the test is $99\%$ reliable in detecting the cancer in an individual that has it
  3. the test yields false positive results in $5\%$ of the cases where an individual is healthy

If someone's test came back positive, what's the probability of them having the cancer?

The visual solution involves figuring out you want to find out the size of the $A \land B$ box in relation to the size of the containing $B$ box.


I have a vague recollection that if you plug in some well-chosen numbers for the reliability of the test, the results will counterintuitively tell you that the test gives you no information at all. That is, it's possible for $P(A|B) = P(A)$.

$\endgroup$
1
  • $\begingroup$ Eg. when A and B are independent events, then P(A, B) = P(A)*P(B). In this case P(A|B) = $\frac{P(A, B)}{P(B)}$ = $\frac{P(A)*P(B)}{P(B)}$ = P(A) $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 16, 2015 at 10:35
10
$\begingroup$

I hate just posting a link (I do not have enough reputation to comment), but Zvezdelina Stankova provided a nice problem which is only approachable if you draw the right picture. See YouTube Video.

$\endgroup$
2
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ her words.. "this is an amazing construction..." $\endgroup$
    – janmarqz
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 20:00
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ Being a spoilsport here. This is accessible within the first sketch she provides, using only elementary geometry. Identify $\alpha, \beta$ and $\gamma$ with the angles in the upper left corner: The $45^\circ$-angle is easy to see and $\gamma$ is the upper of the three angles in the upper left corner by alternate angles. For the remaining pair, note that there are two triangles that share the $135^\circ$-angle and have side ratios $1:\sqrt 2$ and $\sqrt 2 : 2$ respectively. So they are similar and $\beta agrees with the remaining angle in the upper left corner. $\endgroup$
    – blue
    Commented Aug 24, 2015 at 0:32
10
$\begingroup$

I'm trying something of a paradox here: provide an answer to why diagrams are helpful without actually providing the diagram.

Consider this problem:

On a chess board, is there a way for a knight to move from one corner to the opposing corner touching each square exactly once? Say, from a1 to h8.

If you draw a chess board you notice that opposite corners are of the same color. You further notice that a knight changes the color of its square with each move. Touching each square once requires the knight to make 63 moves, after which it ends up on a square with opposite color. So the answer is: no, there is no solution.

$\endgroup$
8
$\begingroup$

Vladimir Arnold,
Huygens and Barrow, Newton and Hooke
Pioneers in mathematical analysis and catastrophe theory from evolvents to quasicrystals

Find the limit: $$\lim_{x\to 0} \frac {\sin(\tan x) - \tan(\sin x)} {\arcsin(\arctan x) - \arctan(\arcsin x)}$$

Well, using Taylor series expansion is practically impossible, but it is the limit of the form $$\lim_{x\to 0} \frac { f(x) - g(x) } { g^{-1}(x) - f^{-1}(x) }$$ and moreover $f(0)=g(0)=0, f'(0)=g'(0)=1$.

After that you just look at the graph (picture from the same book): enter image description here

If the graphs of non-coincident analytic functions $f$ and $g$ touch the line $y=x$ at the origin (Fig. 37), then the ratios $|AB|/|BC|$ and $|BC|/|ED|$ tend to one as $A$ tends to the origin. Therefore the required limit of the ratio $|AB|/|D′E′|$ is equal to one.

$\endgroup$
1
  • $\begingroup$ I think $\arcsin(\arctan x)$ should be $\arctan(\arcsin x)$. $\endgroup$
    – user5402
    Commented Oct 2, 2016 at 12:00
6
$\begingroup$

I can think of some elementary examples.

If we want to find the number of natural numbers below 1000 not divisible by 2,3, or 5, drawing a Venn diagram makes it much much easier.

If we have a random variable $X$ and want to find the distribution of $Y = \sin^2(X)$, it is very helpful to sketch the graph $y = \sin^2(X)$.

Counting the number of solutions to the simultaneous equations $\sin(x-y) = 0$, $x^2 + y^2 = \pi^2$ is very easy with a diagram.

$\endgroup$
3
$\begingroup$

Proving the triangle inequality for this metric, for example: $X = \{A,B,C,D\}$, and $d: X \times X \to \Bbb R$ putting $d(p,p) = 0$ for all $p \in X$, $d(p,q) = d(q,p)$ for all $p,q \in X$, and:

$$d(A,B) = d(A,C) = d(B,C) = 2, \qquad d(A,D) = d(B,D) = d(C,D) = 1.$$ Here's a picture:

enter image description here

$\endgroup$
1
  • 5
    $\begingroup$ The triangle equality is automatically satisfied for any distance function $d$ where $d(x,x)=0$ and $d(x,y)\in[1,2]$ when $x\ne y$. Arguably the diagram here makes it harder to notice this general truth. $\endgroup$ Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 0:10
3
$\begingroup$

enter image description here

The diagram deals with the upper sum of Riemann integral.. The criteria for Riemann integrablity,

$$U(P,f)-L(P,f)<\epsilon$$ is hard to realise. But with the diagram its highly easy.

$\endgroup$
2
$\begingroup$

I've seen something like the following posted as a question here:

Consider the binary relation $R$ on $\{1,2,3,\ldots,8,9,10\}$ given by $$ R=\{(1,4),(1,9),(1,10),(2,3),(3,5),(3,7),(4,6),(5,8),(5,9),(6,10),(7,8)\}$$ Find the transitive symmetric closure of $R$.

It's much more intuitive to draw a graph and find its connected components than to try keeping track of everything symbolically.

Also, more or less all of graph theory, as hinted by the very name of the field.

$\endgroup$
0
$\begingroup$

Look for a schematic view of the solid Klein bottle?

enter image description here

$\endgroup$
2
-6
$\begingroup$

Almost without words enter image description here

coordinates change and tangent basis change on a surface

$\endgroup$
6
  • $\begingroup$ left two $\Sigma$ 's local-GPS s, $\lambda$ is a local-coordinate system. right modern differential calculus code to control basis change on surface-tangent-vector space $\endgroup$
    – janmarqz
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 19:30
  • $\begingroup$ I fail to see how this goes in the "undergraduate mathematics range" $\endgroup$
    – nico
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 22:53
  • $\begingroup$ @nico, do you realized that there is an "undergraduated advanced" in geometry-algebra and analysis? maybe you aren't a mathematician $\endgroup$
    – janmarqz
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 23:15
  • 11
    $\begingroup$ No I am not a mathematician, but I took math courses in my undergrad and I wouldn't have a clue of what I am looking at, especially because you did not even state what the problem here is that is made much easier if you add a graph. Sorry but, whether I am a mathematician or not, this is a bad answer (that, however could be improved a lot, just like your other answer). $\endgroup$
    – nico
    Commented Jan 14, 2015 at 23:32
  • $\begingroup$ look man, understand your point. But always-anytime-anyone can ask for more details, even beyond me there're more people can give more meaning to this picture. $\endgroup$
    – janmarqz
    Commented Jan 15, 2015 at 2:13

You must log in to answer this question.

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged .