3
$\begingroup$

A real closed field can be ordered in one and only one way, and is therefore provided with a unique order topology. Given any infinite cardinal number k, does there always exist a real closed field F (whose cardinal number is greater than k), such that no non-empty subset of F having a cardinal number not greater than k has a limit point in F? The criterion for a point of F to be a limit point of a subset of F is dtermined by the order topology of F. Since we are dealing here with arbitrarily large cardinal numbers, let us assume that we are working within the set theory ZFC.

$\endgroup$
3
  • $\begingroup$ If I understand your question correctly, won't the ultrapower of $\kappa^+$-many copies of $\mathbb{R}$ over a regular ultrafilter work? $\endgroup$ Commented May 18, 2013 at 19:03
  • $\begingroup$ See related question: mathoverflow.net/questions/72612/… $\endgroup$ Commented May 18, 2013 at 19:03
  • $\begingroup$ Any $\kappa^+$-saturated real-closed field has the property you asked for. Since you allow the field to be significantly larger than $\kappa^+$ if necessary, there's no difficulty producing such fields. $\endgroup$ Commented May 18, 2013 at 19:12

2 Answers 2

4
$\begingroup$

If $\delta$ is the cofinality of an ordered field $F$, that is, the size of the smallest unbounded subset of $F$, then every point of $F$ fills a cut of type $(\delta,\delta)$. In other words, every point in $F$ is the limit of an increasing $\delta$ sequence from below and a decreasing $\delta$ sequence from above. One can see that this is true of $0$ by inverting the elements of a strictly increasing positive unbounded $\delta$ sequence; and then one can translate this sequence from $0$ to any other point for the general conclusion.

It follows that any set with a limit point must have size at least $\delta$, and consequently any set of size less than $\delta$ has no limit points in $F$.

It is easy to make fields of any desired cofinality, just by forming a chain of elementary extensions of that length, adding new points above at each step.

$\endgroup$
6
  • $\begingroup$ The extensions don't have to be elementary---any field extensions will do, as long as they get strictly taller each step. If you extend $\delta$ many times and $\delta$ is regular, then you will get a field of cofinality $\delta. $\endgroup$ Commented May 18, 2013 at 20:33
  • $\begingroup$ Many thanks for this helpful information. If (x(1),y(1)) and (x(2),y(2)) are elements of F^2, then the formula: ((x(2)-x(1))^2)+((y(2)-y(1))^2)^(1/2) satisfies all the axioms for a metric on the "space" F^2, although the the resulting "distance" is a non-negative element of F and not necessarily a non-negative real number. Of course if F is sufficiently large, then F^2 is not metrizable (in the classical sense) and although it is dense in itself, it is not "complete". $\endgroup$ Commented May 19, 2013 at 14:56
  • $\begingroup$ My question about limit points arises in trying to work out whether- and if so, how-it might be possible to define some sort of "completion" for F^2 that still allows the "metric" that we have defined to exist. $\endgroup$ Commented May 19, 2013 at 15:07
  • $\begingroup$ In that case, you may be interested in: mathoverflow.net/questions/10870/…. $\endgroup$ Commented May 19, 2013 at 15:59
  • $\begingroup$ Joel, in reference to that question: Given any metric space Y (in the classical sense) and a set R* of standard and non-standard real numbers (which I assume is some real closed field like F in my question) how does one define the non-standard analogue Y* of Y? If d,d* are the respective distance funcions of Y,Y*-how does one define d* when d is given? Many standard metrics involve functions which are exponential or inverse trigonometric and which could cause difficulties when one tried to extend them to larger real closed fields. $\endgroup$ Commented May 20, 2013 at 18:38
1
$\begingroup$

Notice: I thought you would require the field to be of cardinality $k^+$. In that case the proof uses the generalised continuum hypothesis. But without this restriction it is completely unnecessary. The construction is similar to the construction of “the” hyperreals (you might get “them” in the case $\kappa=\omega$).

I can prove it assuming the generalised continuum hypothesis. By the upwards Löwenheim-Skolem theorem there is always a real closed field of cardinality $k^+=2^k$. By induction we can now prove that for every cardinal $\lambda\le k$ there exists a real closed field of cardinality $k^+$ such that every subset of cardinality at most $\lambda$ is bounded. Obviously every finite subset of such a field is bounded. Now consider an infinite cardinal $\lambda\le k$ and assume that for every $\mu<\lambda$ there exists a real closed field $F_{\mu}$ of cardinality $k^+$ such that all subsets less than or equal $\mu$ are bounded and $F_\mu\subset F_\nu$ for $\mu<\nu<\lambda$ and $F_\mu=F_\nu$ for $\mu,\nu$ finite. Now choose an ultraproduct $F$ of all the $F_{\left|\alpha\right|}$ indexed by ordinals $\alpha\in\lambda$ with respect to an ultrafilter which contains all complements of sets of smaller cardinality than $\lambda$. All the $F_\mu$ for $\mu<\lambda$ can be embedded into $F$. The cardinality of $F$ can be approximated by $k^+\le\left|F\right|\le \left(k^+\right)^\lambda=k^+$. It remains to be proven that every subset of $F$ of cardinality at most $\lambda$ is bounded. Choose a well-order $\left(a_\alpha\right)\_{\alpha\in\lambda}$ where each $a_\alpha$ represents an element of $F$ given by a sequence. There exists an upper bound $b$: We just have to choose $b\_\beta$ to be an upper bound of all $(a\_\gamma)\_\beta$ for $\gamma\le\beta$. These upper bounds exist because the set $\left\{(a\_\gamma)\_\beta\mid\gamma\le\beta\right\}$ is contained in $A_{\left|\beta\right|}$ and has cardinality than or equal to $\left|\beta\right|$. QED.

$\endgroup$
4
  • $\begingroup$ You don't need the GCH to build fields of your desired cofinality and size. Once you make a taller field at all, you can cut down to a taller one of the same cardinality as the base field by means of the Lowenheim-Skolem theorem. The union of the chain of extensions will then have the desired cofinality. $\endgroup$ Commented May 18, 2013 at 19:55
  • $\begingroup$ You are right, I did not notice that it is easy to guarantee the desired confinality using some formulas in predicate calculus. The proof is much too complicated. $\endgroup$
    – The User
    Commented May 18, 2013 at 20:02
  • $\begingroup$ Is it complicated? To make a field $F$ of cofinality $\delta$, a regular cardinal, one should just form $F$ as $\bigcup_{\alpha\lt\delta} F_\alpha$, where $F_{\alpha+1}$ has some points on top of every element of $F_\alpha$. Such a field $F_{\alpha+1}$ exists by the compactness theorem. These new points are now unbounded in $F$, and any set of size less than $\delta$ is contained in some $F_\alpha$ and hence is bounded, since $\delta$ is regular. $\endgroup$ Commented May 18, 2013 at 20:08
  • $\begingroup$ My proof is much too complicated, not yours, sorry for the confusion $\endgroup$
    – The User
    Commented May 18, 2013 at 20:26

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged or ask your own question.